Philosophy and consciousness 

Total
0
Shares

Heraclitus the dark mystic by [Konstantinos  Giontzis, Vasilis]

Heraclitus the dark mystic

Philosophy tries to understand life, and at the base of it is the understanding that it is not enough to live life in order to understand them, it is the reveres; our personal involvement with our life does not allow us to understand what is happening in them.

Life without an understanding of it, is mechanical, automatic, and superficial. It is the knowing of what is going on in our life which brings it to the level of really living.

We are also alive when we asleep, but we have no knowing, we are only alive physically but not alive in our consciousness. 

If one gets a hard blow on the head, he can become unconscious, he is alive, but without any knowing about it, so for him he is not alive.

If one is kissed by a loved one and he is asleep, was it for him a kiss, if he did not know that it happened? So, to live is to know, life without knowing what goes on is a sleepy, unconscious life.

But philosophy by itself is not enough, a real knowing could only be gotten to by ‘a state of consciousness’, which is expendable, versatile, and has adaptability.

Consciousness and consciousness state are a subjective medium’ that only with it can the philosophy try to understand something about objective reality.

Philosophy is an objective field, without any relation to a particular person. But without a very subjective, very personal consciousness state – it is not possible to penetrate to the more meaningful dimensions of life and existence.

The high level of consciousness of is: opening, expanding and is peeling of the outer layers of that which is in a process of understanding.

An approach to the understanding of life without the proper consciousness state – will be blocked by the walls of: superficiality, one dimensionality, flatness.

Consciousness operates on three perspectives:

  1. To perceive what has been pushed to the sides. The horizontal plan.
  2. To perceive what is bellow, from above. The vertical plan.
  3. To perceive from inside. The depth plan.

On the horizontal dimension, the consciousness expands the narrow borders of perception, to be able to perceive a large spectrum of concepts and subjects. 

On the vertical dimension the consciousness excels above the low, material, linear and flat level, and to understand the higher, more spiritual levels of our life.

On the depth dimension the consciousness peels off the outer layers and to penetrate into the hidden level, the one under the surface, one of those levels is the subconscious. 

So, a proper consciousness state allows one to see reality from above, from the inside and from the wide spectrum which is outside the part that the person is in at any given time. For it is the space, the depth and the height from which we observe something – which allows us a greater understanding. 

Without developed consciousness our perception is:

  1. Locked in a partial segment of reality.
  2. Berried in the lower and material levels of reality.
  3. Being held and stopped in outer plan of what exists in reality. 

Without the mediation of consciousness we perceive reality in its outer parts, in its lower levels and its partial parts.

Without a developed consciousness, philosophy is intellectual, meaningless. It chews again and again what is already known.

From a consciousness view point we walk instead of being able to fly. 

Bibliography:

Baars, B.J. and McGovern, K.(1996) ‘Cognitive views of consciousness: What are the facts? How can we explain them?’, in M. Velmans (ed.) The Science of Consciousness: Psychological, Neuropsychological, and Clinical Reviews, London: Routledge.

Blauert, J.(1983) Spatial hearing: the psychophysics of human sound localization, M.I.T. Press.

Bermúdez, J. L. 1998a. The Paradox of Self-Consciousness. Cambridge MA. MIT Press.

Bermúdez, J. L. 1998b. ‘Philosophical psychopathology’, Mind and Language 13, 287-307.

Chalmers, D.(1995) ‘Facing up to the problem of consciousness’, Journal of Consciousness Studies 2(3): 200-219.

Churchland, P.S.(1988) ‘Reductionism and the neurobiological basis of consciousness’, in A.J.Marcel and E.Bisiach (eds.) Consciousness in Contemporary Science, Oxford: Clarendon Press.

Craig, K.D.(1978) ‘Social modelling influences on pain’, in R.A. Sternbach (ed.) The Psychology of Pain, New York: Raven Press.

Dawkins, M. S. 1998. Through Our Eyes Darkly: Oxford. Oxford University Press.

Dickinson, A. 1980. Contemporary Animal Learning Theory. Cambridge. Cambridge University Press

Dretske, F. 1995. Naturalizing the Mind. Cambridge MA. MIT Press.

Dennett, D.C.(1991) Consciousness explained, Little Brown.

Dennett, D.C and Kinsbourne, M.(1992) ‘Time and the observer: The where and when of consciousness in the brain’, Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15:183-200.

Gardiner, J.(1996) ‘On consciousness in relation to memory and learning’, in M. Velmans (ed.) The Science of Consciousness: Psychological, Neuropsychological, and Clinical Reviews, London: Routledge.

Gillett, G.(1992) ‘Consciousness, intentionality and internalism’, Philosophical Psychology 5(2):173-180.

James, W.(1890) The principles of psychology, New York: Dover. (Reprinted 1950).

Julesz, B.(1971) Foundations of cyclopean perception, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Kant, I.(1781) Critique of pure reason, Trans. by J.M.D. Meiklejohn, London: Dent, 1969.

Kihlstrom, J.(1996) ‘Perception without awareness of what is perceived, learning without awareness of what is learned’, in M. Velmans (ed.) The Science of Consciousness: Psychological, Neuropsychological, and Clinical Reviews, London: Routledge.

Kohler, W.(1966) ‘A task for philosophers’, in P.K. Feyerabend and G. Maxwell (eds.) Mind, Matter and Method: essays in philosophy of science in honour of Herbert Feigl, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

Libet, B.(1996) ‘Neural processes in the production of conscious experience’, in M. Velmans (ed.) The Science of Consciousness: Psychological, Neuropsychological, and Clinical Reviews, London: Routledge.

Mach, E.(1885) Contributions to the analysis of sensations, Trans. by C.M.Williams, The Open Court Publishing Co.,1897.

Melzack, R.(1973) The puzzle of pain. Harmondsworth: Penguin.

Penfield, W. and Rassmussen,T.B.(1950) The Cerebral Cortex of Man, Princeton University Press.

Place, U.(1956) ‘Is consciousness a brain process?’, British Journal of Psychology 47:44-50.

Pribram, K.H.(1979) ‘Behaviorism, Phenomenology and Holism in Psychology: A scientific analysis’, Journal of Social and Biological Structures 2:65-72.

Rentoul, R.(1992) Consciousness, brain and the physical world: a reply to Velmans. Philosophical Psychology, 5(2), 163-166.

Rosenthal, D. M. 1991. ‘Two concepts of consciousness’, in D. M. Rosenthal (Ed.), The Nature of Mind. Oxford. Oxford University Press

Russell, B.(1948) Human knowledge: its scope and its limits, Allen & Unwin.

Searle, J.(1993) ‘The problem of consciousness’, in Experimental and theoretical studies of consciousness‘, Ciba Foundation Symposium No.174, Wiley, Chichester.

Sheikh, A.N., Kunzendorf, R.G. and Sheikh, K.S.(1996) ‘Somatic consequences of consciousness’, in M. Velmans (ed.) The Science of Consciousness: Psychological, Neuropsychological, and Clinical Reviews, London: Routledge.

Sherrington, C.S.(1942) Man on his nature, Cambridge University Press.

Spinelli, E.(1989) The Interpreted World: An introduction to phenomenological psychology, London: Sage.

Velmans, M.(1990) ‘Consciousness, brain, and the physical world’, Philosophical Psychology 3(1):77-99.

—(1991a) ‘Is human information processing conscious?’ Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14(4):651-669.

—(1991b) ‘Consciousness from a first-person perspective’, Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14(4):702-726.

—(1992a) The world as-perceived, the world as-described by physics, and the thing-itself: a reply to Rentoul and Wetherick. Philosophical Psychology, 5(2), 167-172.

—(1992b) Reply to Gillett. Philosophical Psychology, 5(2), 181-182.

—(1993a) ‘A reflexive science of consciousness’, in Experimental and theoretical studies of consciousness‘, Ciba Foundation Symposium No.174, Wiley, Chichester.

—(1993b) ‘Consciousness, causality, and complementarity’, Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16(2):404-416.

—(1996) ‘An introduction to the science of consciousness’, in M. Velmans (ed.) The Science of Consciousness: Psychological, Neuropsychological, and Clinical Reviews, London: Routledge.

Van Gulick, R. 1994. ‘Deficit studies and the function of phenomenal consciousness’ in G. Graham and L. S. Stephens (Eds.), Philosophical Psychopathology. Cambridge MA. MIT Press

Wall, P.(1996) ‘The placebo effect’, in M. Velmans (ed.) The Science of Consciousness: Psychological, Neuropsychological, and Clinical Reviews, London: Routledge.

Wetherick, N.(1992) ‘Velmans on “Consciousness, brain and the physical world”‘, Philosophical Psychology, 5(2), 159-162.

Whitehead, A.N.(1932) Science and the Modern World, Cambridge University Press.

Young, A.W.(1996) ‘Dissociable aspects of consciousness’, in M. Velmans (ed.) The Science of Consciousness: Psychological, Neuropsychological, and Clinical Reviews, London: Routledge

Leave a Reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *

You May Also Like

The philosophical challenge

One of the main problems when we come to engage in philosophy and try to enter the world of philosophical issues is the issue of language.Almost everyone who goes to…
Read more

About: being gullible

From the book of proverb. ספר משלי ספר משלי באותיות ברורות ועם ניקוד מלא. משלי פרק א’ (א) מִשְׁלֵי שְׁלֹמֹה בֶן דָּוִד מֶלֶךְ יִשְׂרָאֵל׃ (ב) לָדַעַת חָכְמָה וּמוּסָר לְהָבִין אִמְרֵי…
Read more

Radical philosophy

The problem with philosophy at large is that it is too average, too mediocre, too simplified. It is easy for it to slide into any ear. It combines and integrates…
Read more

Philosophy in distress

Socrates on his death bed. Real philosophy, the way I understand it, is more than a study and research area, it is a very creative and individualistic field. It is…
Read more